No.
Let's forget the complication of sets of integers, which I brought up, and stick with proofs of induction for propositions concerning all the natural numbers.
The set of all natural numbers with the property that each exceeds 3 and is exceeded by 6 is {4, 5}. It contains only natural numbers, and it is possible to add 1 to each of them, but the number 5 + 1 = 6 is not in the set {4, 5}. And the set {4, 5} is not the set of all natural numbers.
The set of all natural numbers that are evenly divisible by 2 contains only natural numbers, and it is possible to add 1 to each of them, resulting in odd numbers, but the odd numbers are not in the set of even numbers. So the set of all even natural numbers is not the set of all natural numbers even though it is an infinite set containing only natural numbers.
In inductive proofs you are concerned with some property P that you want to prove is true of every natural number.
The set S that you are concerned with is initially defined as the set of all natural numbers with that property, not the set of all natural numbers. At the start, you have not proved that any natural number has property P. The set S could be empty, or finite, or infinite but not include all natural numbers.
So the first step in the proof is to prove that 1 has that property. That does two things. It shows that the set is not empty and that 1 is in the set.
The second step is to prove that, for any number k whatsoever in the set, k + 1 is in the set. (You know from the first step that the set S is not empty.) Of course k + 1 exists and is part of the set of natural numbers, but just being a natural number does not make k + 1 a member of set S. What do we know about k and k + 1? They are both natural numbers and so have all the properties previously proven to belong to all natural numbers, including the property that a natural number is is equal to or greater than 1. Furthermore, because k belongs to set S, it has property P. Now using that information about k and k + 1, prove that k + 1 also has property P and so is a member of the set S. In terms of the proof, nothing is demonstrated by adding 1 to k. We know you can add 1 to k, and that k + 1 is a natural number. You have to prove that k + 1 has property P.
If you prove that k + 1 has property P, then you can say that set S is identical to the set of natural numbers and P is a property of every natural number. I have given now two examples of how to do such a proof. mmm gave you a link that shows examples. The examples are not as simple as just adding 1 to k and saying it equals k + 1. At least my examples were in fact extremely simple ones.
I have not once heard you mention anything in your questions about the property P that defines the members of set S. Set S is not initially defined as the set of natural numbers. Set S is initially defined as the set of natural numbers that have property P. You are defining sets without reference to any defining property and so wandering in a fog. This whole induction process works only for properties that apply to all natural numbers.
I shall give you one more example and then I am going to bed.
PROVE: \(\displaystyle \displaystyle \left(\sum_{i = 1}^ni\right) = \dfrac{n(n + 1)}{2}\ for\ every\ natural\ number\ n.\)
\(\displaystyle Let\ S\ be\ the\ set\ of\ all\ natural\ numbers\ n\ such\ that\ \displaystyle \left(\sum_{i = 1}^ni\right) = \dfrac{n(n + 1)}{2}.\)
\(\displaystyle \displaystyle \left(\sum_{i=1}^1i\right) = 1 = \dfrac{2}{2} = \dfrac{1(1 + 1)}{2}.\)
\(\displaystyle So\ 1 \in S.\)
\(\displaystyle Consider\ an\ arbitrary\ number\ k \in S.\)
\(\displaystyle So\ \displaystyle \left(\sum_{i = 1}^ki\right) = \dfrac{k(k + 1)}{2}\).
\(\displaystyle \displaystyle \left(\sum_{i = 1}^{k+1}i\right) = \left(\sum_{i=1}^ki\right) + (k + 1) =\)
\(\displaystyle \dfrac{k(k + 1)}{2} + (k + 1) = \dfrac{k^2 + k}{2} + \dfrac{2k + 2}{2} = \dfrac{k^2 + 3k + 2}{2} = \dfrac{(k + 1)(k + 2)}{2} =\dfrac{(k + 1)[(k + 1) + 1]}{2}.\)
\(\displaystyle So\ k + 1 \in S.\)
\(\displaystyle So\ S\ is\ the\ set\ of\ all\ natural\ numbers.\)
\(\displaystyle THUS, \displaystyle \left(\sum_{i = 1}^ni\right) = \dfrac{n(n + 1)}{2}\ for\ every\ natural\ number\ n.\)
Edit: I just saw tkhunny's latest post. He is of course right that you can use induction for propositions that are not directly about natural numbers. I had mentioned earlier and given an example of a proposition that did not apply to all natural numbers. In my post above, I am not contradicting tkhunny. I was limiting myself to the case of propositions about all natural numbers. If you cannot grasp the concept of mathematical induction for propositions about the natural numbers, you are not going to grasp it for propositions that vary somewhat from that fundamental pattern.