Please show what you did -- you should know that by now!is it provable the following
[math]\lfloor x^n\rfloor\geq(\lfloor x\rfloor)^n[/math] for all naturals n and reals x
I can prove it for n=2,3,4
But i cannot generilised it to n
Hint: it is provable. Can you post you proof for n=3 and 4?
I would definitely attack this one by cases. For one thing, I am not sure it is even true for negative x. (Not saying it is false; just saying it is not intuitively obvious to me that it is true for negative x.)is it provable the following
[math]\lfloor x^n\rfloor\geq(\lfloor x\rfloor)^n[/math] for all naturals n and reals x
I can prove it for n=2,3,4
But i cannot generilised it to n
Sorry but there is a mistake here it should be;for n=3 we have:
Let x=n+a where n is a natural No and [math]0\leq a<1[/math]then:
[math]\lfloor(n^3+3n^2a+3na^2+a^3\rfloor\geq n^3\Leftrightarrow\lfloor(3n^2a+3na^2+a^3)\rfloor[/math][math]\Leftrightarrow(3n^2a+3na^2+a^3)\geq 0[/math]Now for a=0 we have [math]0\geq 0[/math] which is correct
For [math]a\neq 0[/math] we have:
[math](3n^2+3na+a^2)\geq 0[/math] which is correct
Hence :
[math]\lfloor x^3\rfloor\geq(\lfloor x\rfloor)^3[/math]
how do you know that if x belongs to integers then [math] x^n [/math] belongs to integers as wellI would definitely attack this one by cases. For one thing, I am not sure it is even true for negative x. (Not saying it is false; just saying it is not intuitively obvious to me that it is true for negative x.)
My first case would be the trivial one that n = 1.
My next case would be the trivial one that x is an integer.
[math]x \in \mathbb Z \implies (\lfloor x \rfloor = x \text { and } x^n \in \mathbb Z \implies[/math]
[math]\lfloor x^n \rfloor = x^n = (\lfloor x \rfloor)^n.[/math]
Then I would go for proofs by induction. Based on my first case, we can certainly say
[math]\exists \text { integer } k \ge 1 \text { such that } \lfloor x^k \rfloor \ge (\lfloor x \rfloor )^k \text { for non-integer } x > 0.[/math]
Now see what that entails for k + 1 given that
[math]\exists \text { integer } p \text { such that } 0 \le p < x < p + 1 \implies p^k < x^k < (p + 1)^k.[/math]
Because the integers are closed with respect to multiplication: the product of integers is an integer.how do you know that if x belongs to integers then [math] x^n [/math] belongs to integers as well
yes but how do know that holds for all nBecause the integers are closed with respect to multiplication: the product of integers is an integer.
That depends on what your starting point is in your class.yes but how do know that holds for all n
This is the problem with questions about proofs. We do not know what axioms you start with and what theorems have already been proved prior to the specific theorem you are asking about.yes but how do know that holds for all n
my question was clear how do we know(prove) that [math] x^n[/math] belongs to integers for all nThat depends on what your starting point is in your class.
Presumably you are starting from some definitions and axioms, or perhaps they are just called properties. Closure may just be given, or might have been proved; but you wouldn't be assigned this proof without knowing that it is true.
Please tell us about your class, as well as why you aren't sure that the integers are closed with respect to multiplication.
This is the problem with questions about proofs. We do not know what axioms you start with and what theorems have already been proved prior to the specific theorem you are asking about.
In most courses, you are not expected to prove that the sum of two integers is itself an integer or that the product of two integers is itself an integer. Such propositions are treated as axioms along with commutivity and the distribution law. Your course probably starts by assuming that the integers have the properties of a commutative group with respect to addition and the properties of a commutative monoid with respect to multiplication.
In a foundations course, you might start with just the Peano postulates. In an abstract algebra course, you might start with the axioms and definitions of a semi-group.
yes but behind every definition we must have a theorem of existenceIf you are merely wondering how to prove that [math]x^n[/math] is an integer given x is an integer and n is a non-negative integer, yes, it is a simple proof by mathematical induction..
[math]\text {Given } n \text { is an integer } \ge 0, \text { define }\\ x^n = 1 \text { if } n = 0;\\ x^n = x * x^{(n-1)} \text { if } n > 0.[/math]
[math]\text {Prove, given } x, \ n \in \mathbb Z \text { and } n \ge 0, \text { that } x^n \in \mathbb Z.[/math]
[math]n = 0 \implies x^n = 1 \in \mathbb Z.[/math]
[math]\therefore \exists \text { integer } k \ge 0 \text { such that } x^k \in \mathbb Z.[/math]
[math]\therefore k + 1 \text { is an integer} > 0 \implies x^{(k+1)} = x * x^{\{(k+1)-1\}} = x * x^k.[/math]
[math]x \text { and } x^k \text { are integers} \implies x * x^k \text { is an integer} \implies[/math]
[math]x^{(k+1)} \text { is an integer.}[/math]
Using the structure of the integers and the fact that if [imath]a\in\Re[/imath] then [imath]\exists! k\in \mathbb{N}[n\le a<k+1[/imath].yes but behind every definition we must have a theorem of existence
For example behind the definition of sqrt we have a theorem of existence
behind the definition of logarith we have a theorem of existence e.t.c e.t.c
In our case what would be the theorem of existence for the definition you produced for the definition: [math]x^n=x.x^{n-1}[/math]?
That is plain ridiculous. How can you possibly prove the existence of something that is not defined?yes but behind every definition we must have a theorem of existence
For example behind the definition of sqrt we have a theorem of existence
behind the definition of logarith we have a theorem of existence e.t.c e.t.c
In our case what would be the theorem of existence for the definition you produced for the definition: [math]x^n=x.x^{n-1}[/math]?